Research

Political Legitimacy

The Big Picture

Above your head, vastly removed from your control, the enormous machinery of government operates. It affects almost every part of your life, as well as everyone else’s. Whichever rulers you are subject to, they have a practical impact so persistent and deep that almost nothing else compares. The personal influence you have on this machinery is minuscule, effectively null: even if you live in a liberal democracy, the tiny flake of power given to you—in the form of the vote and other political liberties—cannot be said to make the state’s decisions yours. If you approve of its decisions, then only in the spectatorial way that you cheer on the weather, which is also beyond your power to control. Neither are you equal in power or other social resources to the public officials who rule over you.

This is a cold, unappealing, unromanticised view of what governments do. Nonetheless, it is correct. If we compare this picture against typical normative ideals of equality and liberty, then we can only conclude that government, as it standardly operates, is a tyrannical violation of our natural equality and freedom. There are, to my mind, only two intellectually honest responses to this challenge. First, we could stick to the normative ideals, accept their demands, and accordingly call for the end of all political structures as they currently exist. Perhaps only an anarchist world without any political power is morally acceptable, or perhaps we endorse some other alternative, such as small communes or worker collectives organised along democratic lines. Either way, the status quo must go.

The second response—the one I prefer—is to reject the orthodox versions of the equality and liberty ideals and replace them with a different justificatory standard. In particular, we should assess governments by their outcomes. The enormous power of the state, according to this alternative view, is justified because it implements principles of justice, because it makes us better off, or because it is preferable to the state of nature; whichever option one chooses, it is the products of government we value, not the process. For the instrumentalist, the machinery of the state is coercive and cannot be said to be an instance of autonomy, whether individual or collective, in any meaningful sense; but nonetheless, it can be justified via its effects.

Thus, we should assess governments in the same way we assess tools—they are in the same category as hammers, bridges, or monetary policy. Government is a complex social machine to achieve morally valuable ends. There is nothing mysterious or intrinsically valuable about this machine. All the major, interesting questions belong to what the valued aims are, and whether they are weighty enough to justify their moral costs. The rest is social science and political wisdom in choosing the best means for achieving our aims. This is the view I defend in a nutshell. We can call it instrumentalism.

The Book

The most thorough defence of instrumentalism you can find in my book, An Instrumentalist Theory of Political Legitimacy (Oxford University Press, 2024). To my knowledge, it is the first book-length defence of instrumentalism. There’s a review of it in Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews, which also offers a helpful overview.

Here’s a super-short summary of each chapter:

Articles on Legitimacy

Not all of my research on political legitimacy has been able to make it into the book. In other articles, I have pursued various supporting lines of argument, or issues which are perpendicular to the main themes of the book. Again, here are some impossibly brief summaries of each paper:

The substantive argument of two further other have now been incorporated with no major changes into the book, although they can still be read as free-standing articles. (This article in Law and Philosophy became chapter 2 in the book, this article in Moral Philosophy and Politics was adapted as chapter 7.)

Articles on the Concept of Legitimacy

I have also done some work on the concept of legitimacy. As these claims are located on the conceptual level, I take them in principle to be independent from substantive moral claims.  

Even More

I have also written a longform review of Dorfman and Harel’s book Reclaiming the Public. The review is useful as an inverted mirror for my own position, as they defend a theory which is almost the polar opposite to mine. So read it if you want a sort-of negative deduction of instrumentalism through a strong critique of its opposite.  

Lastly, Laura Valentini and I have authored a textbook chapter on authority (also touching a little on political legitimacy), which offers a neutral and accessible description of the field of contenders. In an article for the Oxford Handbook of Political Obligation, I also survey philosophical positions about the relationship between legitimacy and authority.

Democratic Theory

If the aim of political institutions is to promote justice, then some natural questions concerning institutional design follow. How can we ensure that democratic institutions work well? How should we deal with disagreements over the aims of justice? These and related questions in political epistemology have been my second major area of research.

The guiding idea I have defended is the importance of the epistemic division of labour: democracies can solve the complex practical problems we face, but only if they are institutionally designed in a way that ensures the combination of widely dispersed epistemic competences (Critical Review, here). I have also sketched what this entails for epistemic deference to normative experts (Episteme, here). Roughly, I think that moral deference to political experts is normally fine, even when such deference concerns normative issues.

Other Interests

In general, I am interested in typical topics at the intersection of philosophy and economics. I have been thinking about monetary policy and inflation in particular, but have been undecided what normative theorising contributes here. I am also interested in housing policy.

I have defended the right to roam in print (Journal of Ethics and Social Philosophy, here). The right to roam is a pretty cool feature of Scandinavian legal systems, where you can roam nature at will, even if the land is privately owned. The article offers the first defence of this right in analytic political philosophy.

My very first publication, going back to my writing sample for grad school (!), was on supererogation (Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplements, here).